Document Type : Original Article

Authors

Institute for Cognitive Science Studies

Abstract

The Humean theory of motivation maintains that cognitive states like beliefs lack motivating force. If an agent were to be motivated to perform an action, s/he would necessarily have a preceding desire Φ and a means-end belief that by Ψ-ing she would be able to satisfy Φ. Although different accounts of this theory have been provided so far, in this paper we will examine the account according to which satisfying the preceding desire is the only basis for motivating someone to choose actions. This paper attempts to show that although the Humean theory of motivation as described above is considered a standard view in explaining intentional actions, it may encounter considerable difficulties to make plausible distinctions between the right and wrong kinds of motivations. In order to demonstrate that, we will first explain Bernard Williams’ Humean view and then discuss that ordinary people not only draw distinctions between de re and de dicto motivations, and between self-regarding and other-regarding motivations, but also think that moral agents normally have reasons to be motivated according to the right kind of these motivations in the relevant circumstances. Finally, we shall design a thought experiment to illustrate the point more strikingly. It seems that a plausible theory of motivation in meta-ethics should accommodate these intuitive and common-sensical sorts of distinctions, while the Humean theory of motivation lacks this feature.

Keywords

Main Subjects

  • مولوی، جلال‌الدین محمد بن محمد، (1390). مثنوی معنوی، به تصحیح رینولد ا. نیکلسون، انتشارات هرمس.
  • Alvarez, Maria. (2010). Kinds of Reason: An Essay in the Philosophy of Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • (1984), The Complete Works of Aristotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes, Princton University Press.
  • Brink, David. O. (1992). “A Puzzle about the Rational Authority of Morality”, in Philosophical Perspectives 6: Ethics, James Tomberlin (ed.), Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, pp. 1-26.
  • Dancy, Jonathan. (2000). Practical Reality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Darwall, Stephen. (2016). “Making the Hard Problem of Moral Normativity Easier”, Weighing Reasons, E. Lord and B. Maguire (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Falk, Werner. D. (1947-8). “Ought and Motivation”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 48, pp. 492-510.
  • Finlay, Stephen. and Schroeder, Mark. (2017). “Reasons for Action: Internal vs. External”, In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (Ed.).
  • Foot, Philippa. (1972). “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives”, The Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.
  • Foot, Philippa. (2001). Natural Goodness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hooker, Brad. (2014). Utilitarianism and fairness. In B. Eggleston & D. Miller (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 280-302.
  • Hume, David. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2nd ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Hume, David, (1874-75), “Of the Standard of Taste”, The Philosophical Works of David Hume, edited by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose, London: Longman, Vol 3.
  • Irwin, Terence. H. (2007-2009). The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study. 3 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kant, Immanuel. (2011). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, edited and translated by Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann, Cambridge University Press.
  • Korsgaard, Christine. (1986). “Skepticism about Practical Reason”, Journal of Philosophy 83: 5-25.
  • Korsgaard, Christine. (1996). “From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action”, in Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, Edited by Stephen Engstrom and Jennifer Whiting, New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 203-36.
  • McDowell, John. (1978). ”Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?”, Aristotelian Society Supplemetary Volume, 52: 13-29.
  • McDowell, John. (1979). “Virtue and Reason”, The Monist, 331-350.
  • McDowell, John. (1981). “Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following”, in Steven Holtzman and Christopher Leich, eds., Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule. Routledge, 141-162.
  • Nagel, Thomas. (1970). The Possibility of Altruism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Parfit, Derek. (1997). “Reasons and Motivation”, Proceedings of the Aristotlian Society, supplement. 71: 99-130.
  • Parfit, Derek. (2011). On What Matters, Oxford University Press
  • (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Edited by John M. Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  • Quinn, Warren. (1993). “Putting Rationality in its Place”, in Quinn, Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Pree), 228-55.
  • Rawls, John. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press.
  • Rosati, Connie. S. (2016). “Moral Motivation”, In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (Ed.).
  • Scanlon, Thomas. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Schueler, George. F. (1995). Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Shafer-Landau, Russ. (2003). Moral Realism: A Defence, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Shaver, Robert. (1995). Hume's Moral Theory? History of Philosophy Quarterly, 12(3), 317-331.
  • Smith, Michael. (1994). The Moral Problem, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Stratton-Lake, Philip. (2000), Kant, Duty and Moral Worth, Routledge.
  • White, Nicholas. (2002). Individual and Conflict in Greek Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Williams, Bernard. (1976). “Persons, Character and Morality” in A. O. Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976.
  • Williams, Bernard. (1979). “Internal and External Reasons”, in Rational Action, edited by R. Harrison. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.